1. Introduction
Credibility theory is a quantitative method that insurance companies use to estimate future losses of a policyholder based on the loss experiences of the policyholder as well as the average loss experiences of all policyholders in the rating class. The main reason for combining the two sources of information is that the former is more relevant but also more volatile; the latter is less relevant but more stable. Credibility theory strives for a balance between the relevancy and statistical stability of the data.
In Bayesian credibility, one assumes that the loss from a policyholder in a rating class follows a parametric model with some risk parameter Heilmann (1989), Klugman (1992), Goovaerts (1990), and references therein.
However, varies by policyholders and is modelled by a random variable that follows some prior distribution The Bayesian credibility premium is determined based on the posterior distribution of risk parameter conditional on the loss experiences of the policyholder. For detailed study of Bayesian credibility, one can refer to, for instance,Bayesian credibility is theoretically sound and widely accepted by academics and practicing actuaries. However, as discussed in, for example, Bühlmann (1976), Eichenauer, Lehn, and Rettig (1988) and Deniz, Vazquez Polo, and Bastida (2000), one drawback of Bayesian credibility is that the parametric model as well as the prior distribution have to be specified. These assumptions can affect the resultant premiums greatly, yet it may be difficult to justify. Therefore, they suggested applying robust Bayesian premium methodology when the practitioner is unwilling or unable to choose a functional form for the prior distribution In particular, Eichenauer, Lehn, and Rettig (1988) derived -minimax credibility formula with respect to vague prior information given by moment restrictions on the priors in case of gamma risk models. Deniz, Vazquez Polo, and Bastida (2000) assumed that the loss model is known but the prior distribution of the model parameters is only known to be in some -contamination class. They obtained bounds for the Bayesian credibility premium under several types of premium principles. Gómez-Déniz (2009) assumed that the values of parameters of the prior distribution fall in some intervals, but their exact values are unknown, he proposed a procedure to determine the credibility premium based on the posterior regret -minimax principle, which can be regarded as a methodology between classical Bayesian and robust Bayesian methods.
Bühlmann (1967) introduced “the greatest accuracy” credibility model, in which the Bayesian credibility is approximated by a linear function of the loss experiences and the prior mean (named the credibility premium). Determining the credibility premium only requires up to the second moment information of the model and the prior. One benefit of this is that the resulting premium is less sensitive to model mis-specification (Hong and Martin 2020), another benefit is that the moment parameters are easier to be specified than the whole probability distribution. In fact, they are commonly determined by actuaries’ professional judgements when there is not enough information (data), as in for example, catastrophe insurance/reinsurance.
Further, Bühlmann (1976) studied the credibility problem when the moment information required by credibility premium is known only to a range. He proposed a minimax credibility premium principle based on the game-theoretic framework. Similar to Bühlmann (1976), Hong and Martin (2021) considered a case when the parameters in the Bühlmann credibility formula are known to be in some intervals and proposed a method for determining premium under the framework of imprecise probability. They argued that this method is “doubly robust” because it is less sensitive to model and prior distribution mis-specification.
In this paper, as in for example, Bühlmann (1976), Gómez-Déniz (2009) and Hong and Martin (2021), we study actuarial credibility problem when the information about the prior distribution of the risk parameter is imprecise or vague, so that the actuary cannot specify the exact prior distribution or the moments. However, instead of considering the imprecise information about the prior distribution from robust Bayesian analysis/ imprecise probability point of view, we propose to apply fuzzy set theory (FST).
FST was introduced in Zadeh (1965). It provides a systematic and rigorous mathematical approach to incorporate vague, fuzzy, or incomplete information. In conventional set theory, an element is either a member or not a member of a given set. In FST, however, an element can be a member of a fuzzy set to some degree. For example, in conventional set theory, the set young drivers can be defined to include all drivers whose age are less than, say 20. So a driver can be either a young driver or not - nothing in between. In FST, however, a member in the universe can belong to a set to a certain degree. For example, a 23 years old driver may belong to the fuzzy set young drivers with, say, membership; whereas a 16 years old belongs to the set with membership.
In credibility problems, information about the risk model and the prior distribution of the risk parameters is usually expressed in linguistic terms, such as “the policyholders in this rating class are rather heterogeneous”, or “the number of losses for this line of business are volatile, even when the risk parameter is fixed” (process variance is high). In such situations, actuaries may feel reluctant to assign certain prior distributions with fixed numerical parameters. We argue in this paper that FST can be a useful tool for such problems.
FST was introduced into the insurance and actuarial literature by de Wit (1982) and Lemaire (1990). It was subsequently applied to insurance rate making by Cummins and Derrig (1993), David Cummins and Derrig (1997), Young (1996) and Young (1997), and to risk classification by Derrig and Ostaszewski (1995) and Young (1993). For a comprehensive overview of the applications of fuzzy set theory in insurance and actuarial science, we refer to (Shapiro 2004).
The main contributions of this paper are two-folds:
-
First, we extend the results on robust Bayesian based on the posterior regret Deniz, Vazquez Polo, and Bastida (2000) and Gómez-Déniz (2009) by assuming that the loss distribution is in the exponential dispersion family (EDF) and that the parameters of the prior distributions are TFNs.
-minimax principle in -
Second, we extend the results on robust Bühlmann credibility in Bühlmann (1976) and Hong and Martin (2021) by assuming that the parameters involved are TFNs.
The rest of the paper is structured as follows. Section 2 first introduces basic concepts and results of FST and then reviews some fundamental results of actuarial credibility theory. Section 3 studies the fuzzy Bayesian premium and the fuzzy Bühlmann credibility in great detail. Section 4 illustrates the applications of the developed theory to both hypothetical and real-data examples. Section 5 concludes.
2. Preliminaries
This section reviews some preliminaries of fuzzy set and actuarial credibility theories.
2.1. Fuzzy set theory
We begin by providing a very brief introduction to FST, including fuzzy number and fuzzy arithmetic. For comprehensive review of the theory, please refer to textbooks such as Dubois and Prade (1980), Klir and Yuan (1995) and Zimmermann (1996).
Definition 2.1. Let Zimmermann (1996)
be a collection of objects (universe of discourse). A fuzzy set in is defined as˜A={(x,m˜A(x))|x∈X},
where
called the membership function, represents the grade of membership of inFor example, let
be the set (universe) of drivers of all ages. Then a fuzzy set of young drivers, defined on the universe may be characterized by a membership functionm˜Y(x)={30−x14, 16≤x≤300, Otherwise.
Therefore, a 16-year old driver is a full member of the fuzzy set
and a 23-year old driver is a half member.Definition 2.2. The Aα={x∈X|m˜A(x)≥α}, ∀α∈[0,1].
-cut of a fuzzy set *is a crisp set defined byFor example, the
-cut of the fuzzy set is a crisp setY0.5={x∈R|m˜Y(x)≥0.5}={x|16≤x≤23}.
Definition 2.3. A fuzzy set is convex if its
-cuts of all levels are convex.Definition 2.4. A fuzzy number is a convex and normalized fuzzy set
defined on the real line such that and is piecewise continuous. The real numbers whose membership function take value 1 are called the core of the fuzzy number.It is easy to verify that the fuzzy set of young drivers,
is a fuzzy number. Its core isSince a fuzzy number is a convex fuzzy set on the real line, its Aα=[A_(α),¯A(α)], where are continuously increasing (decreasing) functions of
-cuts are closed intervals. Therefore, we may denote the -cuts of a fuzzy number byOne of the most commonly used types of fuzzy numbers used in practice is triangular fuzzy number, defined as follows.
Definition 2.5. A triangular fuzzy number (TFN)
with representation is a fuzzy number that has the membership functionm˜A(x)={x−ALA−AL,AL≤x≤AAR−xAR−A,A≤x≤AR,
where
is the core, and and are the left and right bounds respectively. We simply writeThe
-cuts of is given by For example,The extension principle introduced by Zadeh (1965) provides a general method for extending non-fuzzy mathematical operations to fuzzy sets.
Let Zadeh (1965), The function leads to a mapping from the vector of fuzzy numbers to a fuzzy set on with the membership function
be fuzzy numbers defined on respectively. Let be a mapping from the Cartesian product to a universe According to the extension principle ofm˜B(y)={supx1,…,xn,y=f(x1,…,xn)min(m˜A1(x1),…,m˜An(xn))if f−1(y)≠∅0if f−1(y)=∅,
where
is the inverse image of We writeIt is usually difficult to obtain explicit expression for the membership function of Jiménez and Rivas (1998), the problems that arise with vague predicates are less concerned with precision and are more of a qualitative type, thus they are generally written as linearly as possible. Grzegorzewski and Pasternak-Winiarska (2014) stated that, complex shapes of FNs can produce drawbacks in calculations or when interpreting the results. Therefore, in actual applications, triangular or trapezoidal FNs are commonly used. Based on the above reasoning, in this paper, we assume that the parameters used in the credibility calculation are TFNs. As shown in our analysis in the sequel, this assumption of TFN leads to formulas that are easy to compute and to interpret.
However, when are TFN, it can sometimes be obtained (approximated). As argued inThe assumption of TFN allows us to apply the following useful results in the literature.
Lemma 2.1 (Buckley and Qu 1990). For let be a TFN with -cuts Let If is continuous, then the -cuts of is given by
Bα={y∈Y|y=f(x1,…,xn),xi∈Aiα}.
In addition, if
is increasing with respect to the first variables and decreases in the last variables, then the -cuts of are given byBα=[B_(α),¯B(α)],
where
B_(α)=f(A1_(α),A2_(α),…,Am_(α),¯Am+1(α),¯Am+2(α),…,¯An(α)),
and
¯B(α)=f(¯A1(α),¯A2(α),…,¯Am(α),Am+1_(α),Am+2_(α),…,An_(α)).
When the function Kaufmann (1986) and de Andrés-Sánchez (2018), it is possible to approximate the result of nonlinear operations on TFNs by a TFN.
is nonlinear in general, it is difficult to obtain an explicit expression for by applying the above results. In such cases, as discussed inDefinition 2.6. Let
be TFNs defined on the universes respectively. A TFN approximation to is defined by whereBT=f(A1,…,An),BLT=minx1,…,xn∈X1×…×Xnf(x1,…,xn),BRT=maxx1,…,xn∈X1×…×Xnf(x1,…,xn).
Similar to Lemma 2.1, we have the following result.
Lemma 2.2. If
is increasing with respect to the first variables and decreasing in the last variables, then the TFN approximation to is given by whereBT=f(A1,A2,…,Am,Am+1,Am+2,…,An),BLT=f(AL1,AL2,…,ALm,ARm+1,ARm+2,…,ARn),BRT=f(AR1,AR2,…,ARm,ALm+1,ALm+2,…,ALn).
Despite its simplicity, this approach has been verified by Kaufmann (1986) and Jiménez and Rivas (1998) to be effective for many nonlinear operations with TFNs. For actuarial/financial applications of the approximation, one is referred to, for example, Tercenõ et al. (2003) and Heberle and Thomas (2014). Lemma 2.2 is instrumental for our analysis in the sequel. In the numerical examples in Section 4, we compare the premium based on Lemma 2.1 and 2.2. The results are very quite similar.
In another aspect, arithmetic operations on fuzzy numbers result in a fuzzy number. However, when using fuzzy set theory to make business decision such as setting premium for an insurance policy, one needs to come up with a crisp number that reflects the information contained in the relevant fuzzy variables. This process is called defuzzification. There are many commonly used defuzzification methods, such as the “center of area (COA)”, the “center of gravity (COG)”, etc. See for example, Chapter 11 of Zimmermann (1996). In this paper, we adopt the “average index” (AI) method introduced in de Campos Ibáñez and González Muñoz (1989).
Definition 2.7. The AI of a FN
is defined byAI(˜A;λ;H)=∫[0,1]((1−λ)A_(α)+λ¯A(α))dH(α),0≤λ≤1,
where
be is a probability distribution onIn the definition, the integrand
represents the weighted average position of the -cuts of The parameter represents the “optimism-pessimism degree” (uncertainty aversion level) of the decision maker. For example, assuming that is the measure of risk with high value representing higher risk, then a pessimistic (uncertainty averse) decision maker will assign a greater value of than a optimistic one. Further, could be interpreted as the average positions of the -cuts of Y by applying weight function Intuitively, a weight of is given to the average -cuts position . For example, with equal weights are given to every -cut level; with more weights are given to levels with higher values of (more likely levels); with where is large, the weights are concentrated to levels close to 1.For
it is straightforward check thatAI(˜A;λ;H1)=12[A+(1−λ)AL+λAR],AI(˜A;λ;H2)=13[2A+(1−λ)AL+λAR],AI(˜A;λ;H12)=13[A+2(1−λ)AL+2λAR],limn→∞AI(˜A;λ;Hn)=A,limn→∞AI(˜A;λ;H1n)=(1−λ)AL+λAR.
AI defuzzification is fairly flexible. In fact, as illustrated in de Campos Ibáñez and González Muñoz (1989), it extends several other commonly used defuzzification approaches, such as center of gravity and center of maximum. The method has been applied in many areas. For actuarial/financial applications, one is referred to Heberle and Thomas (2014), de Andrés-Sánchez and González-Vila Puchades (2017), and references therein.
2.2. Credibility Theory
In this subsection, we review some basics of actuarial credibility theory that will be needed in the sequel.
2.2.1. Classical Bayesian credibility
Let the potential loss from a policyholder (individual risk) be denoted by a random variable
The loss propensity of the individual risk is characterized by an unknown risk parameter so the distribution of is given by The risks in a rating class (risk collective) are heterogeneous and their risk parameters are different. The collection of risk parameters is represented by a random variable which is assumed to have a prior (structural) distributionIn insurance ratemaking, an actuary needs to determine the premium (Heilmann 1989). For example, with which is the net premium principle; with which is the Esscher premium principle.
for a general risk exposure characterized by risk parameter Let be a loss function, which represents the loss sustained by the insurance company when the premium is and the realized loss is Then, the individual risk premium is determined by minimizing the expected value of the the loss function,However, the value of PB(π0)=argmina∈R+Eπ0[LΘ(P(θ),a)], where is an expectation operator assuming that follows distribution Here, the subscript stands for “Bayesian” and is a loss function that represents the insurance company’s “loss” when the true premium should be but the charged premium is On the other hand, if loss experiences of time periods is observed to be then the Bayes premium is calculated by PB(πx)=argmina∈R+Eπ|x[LΘ(P(θ),a)], where is an expectation operator assuming that follows the posterior distribution
is not observable. Thus, before observing a risk exposure’s loss experience, the insurer charges the collective premium, which is given byFor example, with PB(π0)=Eπ0[P(Θ)]=Eπ0[E[X|Θ]], and PB(πx)=Eπx[P(Θ)]=Eπx[E[X|Θ]].
and we haveA classical result in Bayesian credibility is available when the distribution of
is in the Exponential dispersion family (EDF), with the probability density function (p.d.f.)f(x|θ,τ)=exp{τ(xθ−k(θ))}q(x|τ),τ>0,
and the distribution of the risk parameter is its conjugate prior, satisfying
π0(θ)∝exp{x0θ−t0k(θ)}.
For this case, the Bayesian net premium, Landsman and Makov (1998)
is given byPB(πx)=x0+nτˉxt0+nτ=ZBˉx+(1−ZB)μB,
where
ZB=nτt0+nτ
is the credibility factor,
μB=x0t0
is the collective premium, and
ˉx=n∑i=1xi
is the sample mean.
2.2.2. Robust Bayesian credibility
The above result is quite general because the EDF includes many commonly used distributions. However, to apply it, one needs to know the exact values of the parameters Eichenauer, Lehn, and Rettig (1988) and Deniz, Vazquez Polo, and Bastida (2000) for discussions of such approaches. On the other hand, Gómez-Déniz (2009) considered the posterior regret -minimax methodology to deal with prior distribution uncertainties. In particular, the posterior regret of charging a premium for a risk exposure is defined as
of the prior distribution. This requirement can be restrictive and sometimes unachievable. For example, it could be difficult to justify the selected values. Or, in a group decision-making setting, people may have different opinions about the prior distribution. A common approach to solve this problem is to apply the robust Bayesian method. That is, to consider a class of prior distributions and then determine an action from the range of Bayesian actions. For example, one can apply the minimax criterion, where the action is selected to minimize the loss function under the worst-case scenario of the prior distribution. Readers are referred tor(πx,P)=Eπx[LΘ(P(Θ),P)]−Eπx[LΘ(P(Θ),PB(πx))],
which represents the loss of optimality when
is chosen instead of the optimal action The posterior regret -minimax action is defined to beRP(πx)=argminPmaxπ0∈Γr(πx,P).
It was shown in Gómez-Déniz (2009) that is given by
RP(πx)=12(infπ0∈ΓPB(πx)+supπ0∈ΓPB(πx)).
To provide explicit expressions for Gómez-Déniz (2009) further assumed that the family of prior distributions has form (2.6) but the parameters are only known to be in some intervals. Specifically, they consider the family of distributions
Γ1={π0(θ):x(1)0≤x0≤x(2)0,t(1)0≤t0≤t(2)0}.
Then applying (2.7) and (2.8) yields
RP1(πx)=12(x(1)0+nτˉxt(2)0+nτ+x(2)0+nτˉxt(1)0+nτ).
Remark 2.1. According to the Imprecise credibility estimation methodology proposed by Hong and Martin (2021), actuaries will simply provide the interval [x(1)0+nτˉxt(2)0+nτ,x(2)0+nτˉxt(1)0+nτ] as suggested premium and acknowledge the inherent prior uncertainty. The posterior regret -minimax methodology, on the other hand, proposes that the premium equal to the midpoint of the interval.
2.2.3. Bühlmann credibility
Bühlmann (1967) proposed to use a linear function of loss experience of an individual risk, to approximate the individual pure premium in the sense that the quadratic loss function
E[(μ(Θ)−PC(X))2]
is minimized.
To determine
only the following information about the risk model and the prior distribution of risk parameters are needed.μ=E[μ(Θ)],v=E[v(Θ)]and w=Var(μ(Θ)),
where
μ(θ)=E[X|Θ=θ],v(θ)=Var(X|Θ=θ).
With this, we have
PC(x)=ZCˉx+(1−ZC)μ,
where
ZC=nwnw+v
is called the credibility factor.
As discussed in Hong and Martin (2021), in addition to its intuitiveness and simplicity, one benefit of using Bühlmann’s credibility premium is that one only needs to specify three parameters and which involves up to second-moment information of the model and the prior. The exact distributional information of the model and the prior are not needed. Therefore, it is less susceptible to model error than pure Bayesian methods.
A common practice to estimate the parameters Klugman, Panjer, and Willmot 2019). However, when data is scarce, one may have to rely on prior knowledge and professional judgment regarding the underlying risk. In addition, if there are more than one decision makers, they may disagree about the selection of the parameters. To allow these uncertainties about the model and parameters, Bühlmann (1976) considered the set of models/priors such that and are in the set
is to apply empirical Bayesian method (e.g.Γ2={(μ,v,w):μL≤μ≤μR,vL≤v≤vR,wL≤w≤wR}.
Under a game-theoretic framework, he showed that there exists a minimax strategy that solves
minα0,α1,⋯,αnmax(μ,v,w)∈Γ2E[(μ(Θ)−α0−n∑i=1αiXi)2].
Much more recently, (Hong and Martin 2021) applied the same assumption in (2.11) and suggested that the actuary can simply present the range of possible credibility premiums (called imprecise credibility estimator)
[min(μ,v,w)∈Γ2PC(x),max(μ,v,w)∈Γ2PC(x)].
It is easy to show that
min(μ,v,w)∈Γ2PC(x)=min{c1,c2,c3,c4}
and
max(μ,v,w)∈Γ2PC(x)=max{c1,c2,c3,c4}
where
c1=nvR/wL+nˉx+vR/wLvR/wL+nμL,c2=nvR/wL+nˉx+vR/wLvR/wL+nμR,c3=nvL/wR+nˉx+vL/wRvL/wR+nμL,c4=nvL/wR+nˉx+vL/wRvL/wR+nμR.
Hong and Martin (2021) argued that the “imprecise credibility premium” in (2.12) is doubly-robust, with respect to the choice of model and prior distribution.
3. Fuzzy Credibility
In this section, we introduce a novel approach of determining credibility premium based on FST. Section 3.1 discusses fuzzy Bayesian credibility and Section 3.2 discusses fuzzy Bühlmann credibility.
3.1. Fuzzy Bayesian credibility
In this section, as in Gómez-Déniz (2009), we assume that the loss distribution is in the EDF family and the distribution of the risk parameter is the conjugate prior. Gómez-Déniz (2009) assumed that the values of the prior distribution parameters, and are within certain intervals. Here, we assume that they are represented by TFNs and Then the fuzzy Bayesian net premium is given by
˜PB(πx;F)=˜x0+nτˉx˜t0+nτ,
where the arithmetic operators, such as addition and division, in fact stand for fuzzy arithmetic operations, which follow the extension principle of Zadeh (1965). For simplicity, we just use regular arithmetic operation symbols in this paper.
Let the
-cuts of and be denoted byx0α=[x0_(α),¯x0(α)]andt0α=[t0_(α),¯t0(α)],
respectively, then by (2.2) and (2.3), the
-cuts of isPB(πx;F)α=[x0_(α)+nτˉx¯t0(α)+nτ,¯x0(α)+nτˉxt0_(α)+nτ],0≤α≤1.
and the AI of
is given byAI(˜PB(πx;F);λ)=(1−λ)∫10x0_(α)+nτˉx¯t0(α)+nτdH(α)+λ∫10¯x0(α)+nτˉxt0_(α)+nτdH(α),
which can be numerically evaluated in general.
To simplify calculation and provide intuition, we next provide the analytical form of the TFN approximation of the fuzzy Bayesian premium.
Proposition 3.1. Assuming that
and are TFNs having representations and respectively, then the fuzzy Bayesian premium can be approximated by a TFN˜PB(πx;F)≈(PLB(πx), P0B(πx), PRB(πx)),
where
PLB(πx)=xL0+nτˉxtR0+nτ=ZLBˉx+(1−ZLB)μLB,
with
andP0B(πx)=x0+nτˉxt0+nτ=Z0Bˉx+(1−Z0B)μ0B,
with
and andPRB(πx)=xR0+nτˉxtL0+nτ=ZRBˉx+(1−ZRB)μRB, with and
The AI of
with is given byAI(˜PB(πx;F);λ)=12[P0B(πx)+(1−λ)PLB(πx)+λPRB(πx)],
where
Proof. It is easy to see from (3.1) that
is increasing in and decreasing in Then applying Lemma 2.2 yields (3.3). Equation (3.4) is obtained by applying (2.5).Observe that the AI of the fuzzy Bayesian net premium contains information for both its core and the boundaries, as well as the uncertainty aversion level of the decision maker that is represented by the parameter Gómez-Déniz (2009).
This provides a more flexible approach than the posterior regret -minimax result proposed inRemark 3.1. Proposition (3.1) only provides formulas for AI of
with As shown in Section 2.1, other forms of can be applied, which would result in premium being different combinations of the bounds and the core of In particular,limn→∞AI(˜PB(πx;F);λ,H(α)=αn)=P0B(πx),
which is the classical Bayesian premium.
In addition,
limn→∞AI(˜PB(πx;F);λ,H(α)=α1n)=(1−λ)PLB(πx)+λPRB(πx),
which is a generalization of the posterior regret (Gómez-Déniz 2009).
-minimax result proposed in3.2. Fuzzy Bühlmann credibility
In this section, we assume that the three parameters in the Bühlmann credibility are positive TFNs with representations
andDirectly applying (2.10) would yield a fuzzy Bühlmann credibility estimator
˜PC(x;F)=n˜w˜v+n˜wˉx+˜v˜v+n˜w˜μ.
Let the
-cuts of and be denoted byμα=[μ_(α),¯μ(α)],vα=[v_(α),¯v(α)]and wα=[w_(α),¯w(α)],
respectively, then by (2.1), the
-cuts of isPC(x;F)α=[min{c1α,c2α,c3α,c4α},max{c1α,c2α,c3α,c4α}],0≤α≤1,
where
c1α=n¯v(α)/w_(α)+nˉx+¯v(α)/w_(α)¯v(α)/w_(α)+nμ_(α),
c2α=n¯v(α)/w_(α)+nˉx+¯v(α)/w_(α)¯v(α)/w_(α)+n¯μ(α),
c3α=nv_(α)/¯w(α)+nˉx+v_(α)/¯w(α)v_(α)/¯w(α)+nμ_(α),
c4α=nv_(α)/¯w(α)+nˉx+v_(α)/¯w(α)v_(α)/¯w(α)+n¯μ(α).
With this, the membership function of the fuzzy Bühlmann credibility premium
can be determined numerically.Equations (3.7) to (3.10) provide us a way to determine the membership function of
However, it does not provide much intuition. Next we provide an explicit form for the fuzzy Bühlmann credibility premium by approximating it using a TFN.Since it is more natural to express the credibility premium as a linear function of the mean loss experience and the prior mean, we rewrite (3.5) as
˜PC(x;F)=˜ZCˉx+(1−˜ZC)˜μ,
where
˜ZC=n˜k+n
and
It is understood that the two in (3.11) always take the same value.Firstly, since
is monotone in and by (2.4), it can be approximated by a TFN wherekL=vLwR, k0=v0w0 and kR=vRwL.
Then, because the credibility factor
is monotone in it can be approximated by a TFN with representation˜ZC=(ZLC,Z0C,ZRC),
where
ZLC=nn+kR, Z0C=nn+k0 and ZRC=nn+kL.
As a result, the AI of
is given byAI(˜ZC,λ)=12(Z0C+(1−λ)ZLC+λZRC).
Now, because
is increasing in if is positive and decreasing in if is negative, it cannot be approximated by directly applying Lemma 2.2. Therefore, we next propose a method to get around this. We start with the simple case when is a crisp number, which leads to the following result.Proposition 3.2. Assume that
is crisp and are TFNs. Let the fuzzy credibility be given by (3.12), then we have-
When ˜PC(x;FZ;1)=(PLC(x;FZ;1),P0C(x;FZ;1),PRC(x;FZ;1)), where PLC(x;FZ;1)=ZRCˉx+(1−ZRC)μ0, P0C(x;FZ;1)=Z0Cˉx+(1−Z0C)μ0, and PRC(x;FZ;1)=ZLCˉx+(1−ZLC)μ0.
can be approximated by the TFN -
When ˜PC(x;FZ;2)=(PLC(x;FZ;2),P0C(x;FZ;2),PRC(x;FZ;2)), where PLC(x;FZ;2)=ZLCˉx+(1−ZLC)μ0, P0C(x;FZ;2)=Z0Cˉx+(1−Z0C)μ0, and PRC(x;FZ;2)=ZRCˉx+(1−ZRC)μ0.
can be approximated by the TFN
In addition, the AI of the fuzzy premium
is given byAI(˜PC(x;FZ);λ)={AI(˜ZC,λ)ˉx+(1−AI(˜ZC,λ))μ0,ˉx>μ0AI(˜ZC,1−λ)ˉx+(1−AI(˜ZC,1−λ))μ0,ˉx<μ0.
Proof. When
is increasing in and the smallest and largest values of credibility premium are and respectively. Applying Lemma 2.2 yields (3.14). When is decreasing in Applying Lemma 2.2 leads to (3.13).Further, applying (2.5) to (3.13) and (3.14), we could obtain the corresponding AI values. For example, when
we haveAI(˜PC(x;FZ;1);λ)=12(P0C(x;FZ;1)+(1−λ)PLC(x;FZ;1)+λPRC(x;FZ;1))=12(Z0Cˉx+(1−Z0C)μ0+(1−λ)(ZRCˉx+(1−ZRC)μ0)+λ(ZLCˉx+(1−ZLC)μ0))=AI(˜ZC,1−λ)ˉx+(1−AI(˜ZC,1−λ))μ0.
Similar calculation can be applied for the case
Remark 3.2. Interestingly, for
with the credibility factor depends on the value of relative to If then Therefore, equation (3.15) indicates that more weight (credibility) is assigned to the loss experiences when than when This result makes sense because in our setting, means that the decision maker is pessimistic (uncertainty averse) and thus tends to penalize worse-than-expected loss experiences more than to award better-than-expected loss experiences. The opposite is true when When the credibility factor is simply regardless of the value ofNext, we consider the case when all three parameters
and are TFNs. By considering the cases of and separately, we have the following result.Proposition 2.3. When
are TFNs, then we have the following results.-
When ˜PC(x;FZ,μ;1)=(PLC(x;FZ,μ;1),P0C(x;FZ,μ;1),PRC(x;FZ,μ;1)), where PLC(x;FZ,μ;1)=ZRCˉx+(1−ZRC)μL, P0C(x;FZ,μ;1)=Z0Cˉx+(1−Z0C)μ0, and PRC(x;FZ,μ;1)=ZLCˉx+(1−ZLC)μR.
the fuzzy credibility premium can be approximated by the TFN -
When ˜PC(x;FZ,μ;2)=(PLC(x;FZ,μ;2),P0C(x;FZ,μ;2),PRC(x;FZ,μ;2)), where PLC(x;FZ,μ;2)=ZLCˉx+(1−ZLC)μL, P0C(x;FZ,μ;2)=Z0Cˉx+(1−Z0C)μ0, and PRC(x;FZ,μ;2)=ZLCˉx+(1−ZLC)μR.
it can be approximated by the TFN -
When ˜PC(x;FZ,μ;3)=(PLC(x;FZ,μ;3),P0C(x;FZ,μ;3),PRC(x;FZ,μ;3)), where PLC(x;FZ,μ;3)=ZLCˉx+(1−ZLC)μL, P0C(x;FZ,μ;3)=Z0Cˉx+(1−Z0C)μ0, and PRC(x;FZ,μ;3)=ZRCˉx+(1−ZRC)μR.
it can be approximated by the TFN
Further, the AI of resulting fuzzy premium
is given byAI(˜PC(x;FZ,μ);λ)={AI(˜ZC,1−λ)ˉx+12((1−Z0C)μ0+(1−λ)(1−ZRC)μL+λ(1−ZLC)μR), ˉx<μL12(Z0C+ZLC)ˉx+12((1−Z0C)μ0+(1−λ)(1−ZLC)μL+λ(1−ZLC)μR), μL<ˉx<μRAI(˜ZC,λ)ˉx+12((1−Z0C)μ0+(1−λ)(1−ZLC)μL+λ(1−ZRC)μR), ˉx>μR
Proof. Firstly, when
the smallest and largest values of credibility premium are and respectively. Applying Lemma 2.2 yields (3.16).Similarly, when
the smallest and largest values of credibility premium are and respectively. Applying Lemma 2.2 results in (3.17).Finally, when
the smallest and largest values of credibility premium are and Applying Lemma 2.2 yields (3.18).With (3.16), (3.17) and (3.18), the corresponding AI values can be calculated straightforwardly. For example, we have
AI(˜PC(x;FZ,μ;1);λ)=12(P0C(x;FZ,μ;1)